Death Penalty Jurisprudence: An Attempt to Persuade as to the Nature of Justice
Do you think you have the right to retaliation against your country and its
laws?...You must either persuade it or obey its orders, and endure in silence
whatever it instructs you to endure, whether blows or bonds, and if it leads
you into war or to be wounded or killed, you must obey. To do so is right, and
one must not give way or retreat or leave ones post, but both in war and
in courts and everywhere else, one must obey the commands of ones city
and country, or persuade it as to the nature of justice.1
- Crito, Plato
Death is the end to our corporeal existence on this world.2
Laws against causing the death of another have followed human existence throughout
the ages.3 Perhaps the most profound law
against murder is the sixth commandment of the Old Testament.4
And yet, ancient and modern societies have continued to utilize capital punishment
in their criminal justice systems. Indeed, two of the earliest, most renowned
death sentences and subsequent executions were those of Socrates and Jesus of
Nazareth.5 Ironically, their deaths came
as a result of their spoken word.6 While
the crimes for which capital punishment is sought are no longer so totalitarian
in most modern societies, capital punishment continues to be an accepted form
of criminal justice.7 Despite a worldwide
trend toward abolition, the United States stands out as a stalwart advocate
of capital punishment.8 While the U.S. Supreme
Courts position on capital punishment has fluctuated in the last quarter-century,
the Courts current position is that capital punishment does not violate
the Constitution.9 Despite this, a minority
of states have chosen to abolish the use of capital punishment.10
Lest one perceive this as a trend, New York recently reinstated the death penalty.11
In addition, the number of individuals executed continues to increase.12
This essay focuses on the jurisprudential arguments utilized in Connecticut
to support the continued administration of capital punishment. Part I of this
essay will summarize the U.S. Supreme Courts response to capital punishment
challenges. Part II will discuss the arguments for and against capital punishment
in the State of Connecticut.
I. Federal Jurisprudence
In 1976, the Supreme Court held the death penalty per se did not violate any
provision of the United States Constitution.13
The Court has continued to reaffirm this interpretation. Gregg v. Georgia
reinstated an interpretation of the Constitution which the court had formerly
affirmed since the founding of our country. Only for a period of four years
had the Court held the death penalty unconstitutional.14
Since Gregg, the Court has continued to clarify when the death penalty
may be administered and the procedural safeguards which must be strictly followed
in order for a death penalty to pass constitutional muster. Except for these
criteria, the death penalty does not violate the United States Constitution.
A. Pre- Furman
As early as 1878, the Supreme Court held that the death penalty did not violate
the Eight Amendments guarantee against cruel and unusual15
punishment as long as the method by which a sentence of death is carried
out is not cruel and unusual.16
The Court later defined cruel punishment as that which involves torture
or a lingering death and that the Eighth Amendment implies...something
inhuman and barbarous, something more than the mere extinguishment of life.17
The Court again held that the punishment of death is not cruel, within
the meaning of that word as used in the Constitution."18
In Weems v. United States, the Court tied what constitutes cruel
to something more than a static definition.19
It held that the Eighth Amendment is progressive and does not prohibit
merely the cruel and unusual punishments known in 1689 and 1787, but may acquire
wider meaning as public opinion becomes enlightened by humane justice.20
Despite the Courts refusal to hold the death penalty unconstitutional,
some members of the Court began to suggest limits as to which crimes would justify
such a penalty.21 In addition, the Court
began to recognize some other limitations on when and how a death penalty may
be sought.22 However, the Court by and
large embraced a deferential attitude toward state procedure where the death
penalty was concerned.23 Indeed, just before
the decision in Furman v. Georgia, the Court held that entrusting a jury
with standardless discretion to impose a sentence of death did not violate the
Constitution of the United States.24
B. The Furman v. Georgia25 and Gregg
v. Georgia26 Thematic Pronouncements
In Furman, the Supreme Court was concerned with the arbitrary and capricious
way in which death penalties were administered and the insufficient number of
procedural safeguards in the states.27
In response, the Court effectively overturned every states capital punishment
system.28 While some suggest that Furman
declared the death penalty unconstitutional, others more accurately suggest
that Furman merely held the existing administration of the death penalty
unconstitutional.29 The Court concluded
that the imposition and carrying out of the death penalty in these cases
constitute cruel and unusual punishment in violation of the Eighth and Fourteenth
Amendments.30 Since each justice
filed his own opinion, it is difficult to graph any agreed upon set of guidelines
from Furman.31 As a result, it appears
that courts most often refer to those opinions that were based on the narrowest
grounds.32 Despite this difficulty, thirty-five
states enacted legislation to reintroduce death penalty schemes which conformed
with Furmans mandate.
Four years after Furman, the Court in Gregg authorized a
virtual return to the days before Furman v. Georgia, and to a regime
in which the jury has unfettered discretion to elect death.33
Thus, any protection an individual has from the death penalty per se must not
be sought from the United States Constitution, but rather from provisions within
state constitutions or statutes.34
II. Connecticut Death Penalty Jurisprudence
The Supreme Court of Connecticut has held that its constitution may afford its
citizens greater protection than that of the United States Constitution.35
Nevertheless, the State of Connecticut continues to uphold the constitutionality
of capital punishment as a means to administer justice.36
Thus, the Connecticut Constitution does not afford its citizens any greater
protection of their lives than does the United States Constitution.37
The following section introduces the analysis which the Connecticut Supreme
Court employs when addressing a state constitutional issue for the first time.
This introduction is followed by a discussion of various arguments presented
before the court which both support and oppose the use of capital punishment.
A. The Analysis for Novel State Constitutional Issues
The Connecticut Supreme Court has identified six factors to be considered when
addressing a state constitutional issue for the first time. These include: (1)
the text of the constitutional provisions; (2) related Connecticut precedents;
(3) persuasive federal precedents; (4) persuasive precedents of other state
courts; (5) historical insights into the intent of our constitutional forebearers;
and (6) contemporary understandings of applicable economic and sociological
norms.38 While the court has not
clearly articulated a methodology to be used in applying the Geisler
factors,39 they do provide a foundation
from which to analyze decisions. Indeed, the court has employed all six factors
when it first considered the state constitutionality of the death penalty in
Connecticut.40 Therefore, it is prudent
to be aware of these factors in our discussion of Connecticut death penalty
jurisprudence.
B. State Constitutional Arguments
While the death penalty has been utilized in Connecticut since pre-1650,41
its use,42 and the statutes authorizing
its use, have become more restrictive over the last fifty years.43
Despite this move toward de facto abolition,44
the states death penalty statutes were effectively invalidated by the
United States Supreme Court in Furman v. Georgia.45
In State v. Aillon, the Connecticut Supreme Court acknowledged Furman
and the unconstitutionality of the Connecticut death penalty scheme.46
The court responded by remanding cases on appeal for the limited purpose
of resentencing the defendant to a term of life imprisonment.47
In 1973, the Connecticut legislature reintroduced death penalty legislation48
presumably in accordance with the guidelines suggested in Furman v.
Georgia.49 The legislation was
enacted and codified.50 Interestingly,
only six individuals have received a sentence of death under the statute since
1974.51 Upon hearing challenges to the
constitutional validity of the new statute, the Connecticut Supreme Court found
the new death penalty statute to be valid under the federal guidelines established
in Furman v. Georgia and Gregg v. Georgia.52
However, the court did not address state constitutional issues regarding Connecticuts
death penalty statute until 1994.53 The
court has since addressed additional challenges to the constitutionality of
the death penalty under the state constitution.
In considering challenges to the Connecticut death penalty statute, the Connecticut
Supreme Court has addressed arguments suggesting that the penalty is cruel and
unusual and violates the social compact adopted through Article 1, Section 1
of the Connecticut Constitution. In addition, the court has been presented with
arguments suggesting the death penalty violates the equal protection clauses
and is without a supporting compelling state purpose. While none
of these arguments has succeeded in persuading a majority of the court,54
there are weaknesses in the courts analyses of these arguments.55
It should be noted that there are only two cases where the Connecticut Supreme
Court has heard arguments challenging the validity of the death penalty under
the state constitution. As a result, each of these cases tends to represent
the courts position on particular arguments presented before it.56
1. The Cruel and Unusual Argument
There have been several claims that capital punishment constitutes cruel and
unusual punishment and is therefore prohibited under the Connecticut Constitution.
However, the Connecticut Constitution does not contain a specific prohibition
against cruel and unusual punishment.57
In State v. Ross, the court concluded that, despite the absence of a
specific prohibition against cruel and unusual punishment, the Constitution
does condemn such punishment by incorporating through the due process clauses
those constitutional or quasi-constitutional rights that were recognized
at common law in this state prior to 1818."58
The court further concluded that the due process clauses impliedly prohibit
punishment that is cruel and unusual.59
Despite recognizing a protection against cruel and unusual punishment
under the Connecticut Constitution, the Connecticut Supreme Court has refused
to categorize the death penalty as cruel and unusual. In Ross, the court
employed the Geisler factors to reach this conclusion.60
First, the court concluded that because the Connecticut Constitution specifically
refers to a capital offense in Article I, Section 19,61
the text of the constitution supports capital punishment rather than condemns
it.62 Second, the court stated that Connecticut
case law has recognized the facial constitutionality of the death penalty under
the eight and fourteenth amendments to the federal constitution.63
Here, the court may have misinterpreted the second Geisler factor. Earlier
in Ross, the court had addressed the federal constitutional issues relating
to the death penalty. In addition, the state constitutional issues relating
to the death penalty had been left open until the courts analysis in State
v. Ross.64 Thus, the cases to which
the court cites as related Connecticut precedent were limited to
an analysis of federal constitutional issues. Therefore, it would seem that
the courts use of such Connecticut precedent was inappropriate in the
context of the state constitutional analysis. The conclusion should have been
one which acknowledged the absence of any specifically related Connecticut precedent.65
Third, citing Gregg v. Georgia, the court summarized the federal
response to similar arguments by simply stating the death penalty is not considered
cruel and unusual punishment. Fourth, the court noted precedent in the majority
of sister states which had rejected facial challenges to the death penalty
under their state constitutions.66
Fifth, the court stated that there has been a death penalty statute in Connecticut
since even before 1650.67
Finally, the court reached the Geisler factor which was most relevant
to the defendants claim that the death penalty no longer comports
with contemporary standards of decency and civilization:68
whether the death penalty is no longer constitutional under contemporary
understandings of applicable economic and sociological norms.69
In considering this question, the court rephrased its inquiry as whether the
defendant was correct in his contention that the death penalty is so inherently
cruel and so lacking in moral and sociological justification that it is unconstitutional
on its face because it is fundamentally offense to evolving standards of decency.
The Connecticut Supreme Court has recognized that [c]onstitutional provisions
must be interpreted within the context of the times . . . As one court said:
We must interpret the constitution in accordance with the demands of modern
society or it will be in constant danger of becoming atrophied and, in fact,
may even lose its original meaning.70
The court continued: It is this court's duty to assure that our constitution
does not become a magnificent structure . . . to look at, but totally
unfit for use. Moreover, a constitution is, in Chief Justice John Marshall's
words, intended to endure for ages to come, and, consequently, to be adapted
to the various crises of human affairs.71
In Ross, the court recognized that [j]udicial evaluation of evolving
standards of human decency cannot proceed in a vacuum and that we
should not follow a beaten path.72
However, the court did, in fact, both proceed in a vacuum and follow a beaten
path. By limiting its inquiry to the United States when evaluating evolving
community standards, the court dismissed a worldwide movement to abolish
the use of the death penalty.73 Specifically,
the court missed the opportunity to join the states and world jurisdictions
which have recognized that capital punishment is violative of human rights.74
The court also should have taken more than a cursory glance at statutory language.
An inquiry into the use of the death penalty among sister states would
suggest a different perspective, if not entirely different, from that of the
court.75 Indeed, public opinion must
be gleaned from a societys actual record in carrying out the death penalty.76
Connecticuts record suggests a de facto abolition considering there
has not been an execution since 1960.
In contrast to the majoritys reliance on the legislatures of thirty-seven
states,77 Justice Berdon, in his dissent,
suggested a multi-faceted inquiry into contemporary standards of human decency.
Such an inquiry should include a consideration of (1) whether the punishment
is degrading to the dignity of the human being; (2) whether the punishment is
acceptable to the public; (3) whether the punishment has, in the past, been
administered in an arbitrary and capricious manner; (4) whether the punishment
has been imposed in a discriminatory fashion; (5) whether the punishment serves
any legitimate purpose; and (6) whether the punishment is so final and complete
that error cannot be corrected.78
Justice Berdon argued that the death penalty is inherently degrading to
the dignity of a human being because the physical and psychological
pain associated with it are barbaric and the cruelty of capital
punishment lies not only in the execution itself and the pain incident thereto,
but also in the dehumanizing effects of the lengthy imprisonment prior to execution...79
As to whether the punishment is acceptable to the public, he suggested that
public opinion should be measured objectively in terms of societys
actual record in imposing the death penalty. Such a perspective yields
a history which demonstrates a reluctance to impose the death penalty.80
Justice Berdon also concluded that the death penalty is administered in an arbitrary
and capricious manner,81 is discriminatory
in its effect,82 and serves no legitimate
state purpose.83
Finally, Justice Berdon concluded that the incontrovertible finality of
death is indicative of the cruel and unusual nature of the death penalty. With
evidence demonstrating the mistake-prone nature of the criminal justice system,
Berdon argues that [e]ven if only one innocent life is extinguished in
the process of putting people to death, that one life makes the cost of the
death penalty unacceptable.84 And,
there oftentimes is no way to know whether an innocent was executed
or not because once a defendant is executed there is no forum to evaluate
guilt or innocence.85 Various studies
and reports have documented cases in which a possibly innocent individual was
executed.86 National statistics reveal
that of the 5,580 individuals sentenced to death between 1973 and 1995, thirty-four
percent had their sentence or conviction overturned.87
Other studies document cases in which individuals who were on death row were
later acquitted due to new evidence.88
Connecticut has not escaped such a phenomenon.89
The potential conviction and execution of an innocent individual might indeed
support a conclusion that, as administered, the death penalty is cruel and unusual.
However, the danger in relying on such an argument is that a time may arrive
when innocents are no longer convicted, sentenced, and executed. In such a case,
the death penalty would no longer be cruel and unusual under the innocent
execution argument. In fact, depending on which party has the burden of
proving the purity of the death penalty scheme, such a time may arrive sooner
than later. For example, assume that a court did in fact rule that a justice
system was an inexact science and barred use of the death penalty until the
system was pure90 in its convictions and
sentences. To whom would the court rely to demonstrate the systems purity?
Would legislative measures be enough to demonstrate a perfect (or near perfect)
system? Would defendants be required to show at each trial or appeal that mistakes
still occur? Or, would the state have the burden of proving that the system
was pure? Each scenario brings with it significant consequences. In other words,
the innocent execution argument suggests only the cruel and unusual
nature of the death penalty as it exists today. Regarding a specific defendant,
the delay obtained through a courts acceptance of this argument could
be considered a victory. However, the victory might be hollow when a court later
finds the system is pure.91
In Ross, the Connecticut Supreme Court examined the constitutionality
of Connecticuts death penalty under its state constitution and found it
facially valid. Through the application of the six Geisler factors, the
court found no support for the defendants argument. However, in a more
thorough analysis of Connecticuts history and the contemporary standards
of human decency, Justice Berdon provided a strong dissent in which he concluded
the death penalty is violative of the state constitution.92
The courts limited inquiry into evolving standards of human decency
blinded it to the worldwide movement toward abolition of the death penalty.
Indeed, such a movement emphatically suggests an overwhelming position that
capital punishment is fundamentally offensive to evolving standards of
human decency. Yet, Ross remains the Connecticut Supreme Courts
analysis of whether the death penalty constitutes cruel and unusual argument.
Recently, indeed, this analysis has been reaffirmed.93
2. The Social Compact Argument
The Connecticut Constitution provides that "[a]ll men when they form a
social compact, are equal in rights; and no man or set of men are entitled to
exclusive public emoluments or privileges from the community."94
While the Connecticut Supreme Court has heard arguments invoking the social
compact clause as constitutional support for minimal substinence95
and shelter,96 it was not until State
v. Webb that the argument was used in a constitutional challenge to the
Connecticut death penalty.97 Despite the
courts admonition that the direct infraction of vested rights by
the legislature would be considered as a violation of the social compact,
and within the control of the judiciary,98
the court has refused to validate arguments suggesting that certain statutory
schemes violate the social compact and are thus unconstitutional.99
In essence, the court does not recognize the existence of the particular
vested right argued before it. The failure to recognize a vested
right eliminates any possible violation and quashes any social compact argument.
In its analysis of social compact arguments, the Connecticut Supreme Court
has equated social compact theory with natural law.100
In addition, the court has refused to recognize unenumerated constitutional
rights emanating from either the social compact clause or natural law principles.101
Indeed, the courts examination of the historical role of natural
law in [Connecticuts] constitutional system102
led it to conclude that our forebears did not understand natural law to
be a source of expansive, unlimited rights that civil law was prohibited from
subjecting to substantial statutory restrictions.103
And yet, the court has recognized rights not explicitly enumerated in
the Connecticut Constitution.104 The distinction
may be that unenumerated rights recognized at common law are more worthy than
those considered to have originated from natural law.105
To the Connecticut Supreme Court, only unenumerated rights which are grounded
in or derived from the constitutional text or Connecticuts unique historical
record exist.106 In Webb,
the defendant argued that members of the social compact retain an absolute
natural right to life.107 As we
have observed, the courts examination of capital punishment in Connecticut
history revealed nothing but support for capital punishment and certainly no
evidence of a recognized natural right to life.108
3. The Equal Protection Argument
Many scholars have commented that empirical data suggest a racial bias in the
administration of the death penalty in the United States.109
Despite this, the Connecticut Supreme Court has failed to address the issue
of racism in the administration of the death penalty.110
Scholars have also commented on the arbitrary and capricious manner in which
the death penalty is sought and obtained. This, too, the court seems to evade.
However, the court may not be entirely to blame. While Justice Berdon includes
the issues of racism and arbitrariness within his discussion of the death penalty
as cruel and unusual punishment, it would seem more prudent to graph such arguments
into a separate constitutional claim under the equal protection clauses and
civil rights guarantees in the Connecticut Constitution. To date, this has not
been done.
a. The Purposeful Discrimination Requirement
Such an approach to these issues is not novel.111
In fact, similar arguments have been made before the United States Supreme Court.
In McClesky v. Kemp,112 the defendant
argued that the administration of the Georgia capital punishment system violated
the Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments.113
Specifically, the defendant argued that the Georgia system was administered
in a racially biased manner and introduced a statistical study (the Baldus study)
to demonstrate this bias.114 He claimed
that race had infected the administration of Georgia's statute in two
ways: persons who murder whites are more likely to be sentenced to death than
persons who murder blacks, and black murderers are more likely to be sentenced
to death than white murderers.115
Despite the presumed validity of the Baldus study,116
the Court refused to recognize a valid equal protection claim. First, the Court
held that a defendant must prove purposeful discrimination when alleging an
equal protection violation.117 Second,
the Court held that a defendant must prove that the purposeful discrimination
had a discriminatory effect on him.118
While the Court has allowed statistical studies to be the sole proof
of discriminatory intent and personal, discriminatory effect,119
the Court held that capital punishment cases are different from those cases
where such evidence has been accepted.120
Thus, purposeful discrimination must be proven by the defendant
in order to prevail on an equal protection claim under the Fourteenth Amendment.
Contrary to federal precedent, Sheff v. ONeill121
suggests that the purposeful discrimination requirement would
not be necessary under the Connecticut Constitution. In Sheff, the Connecticut
Supreme Court held that the discriminatory effects122
of the public school system in Hartford, Connecticut violated the Connecticut
Constitution.123 In so doing, the court
rejected the defendants argument urging the court to adopt the federal
standard requiring plaintiffs to prove intentional governmental discrimination
against a suspect class.124 In fact,
the court specifically rejected the analysis relied upon by the Supreme Court
in McClesky.125 First, the court
explained that there is a fundamental right to an education in the Connecticut
Constitution that is absent from the United States Constitution.126
Second, and most relevant to this discussion, the court reasoned that federal
equal protection cases are guided by principles of federalism which are absent
from state constitutional litigation. Thus, the Connecticut Supreme Court held
that school segregation violates the state constitution even without a discriminatory
purpose. This suggests that the Connecticut Supreme Court would not require
a discriminatory purpose where a defendant alleges de facto discrimination in
the administration of capital punishment.
b. Standard of Review
The Connecticut Constitution contains two provisions which have been interpreted
to provide equal protection to Connecticuts citizens.127
In addressing an equal protection challenge under the Connecticut Constitution,
the reviewing court must first determine the standard by which the challenged
statute's constitutional validity will be determined. If, in distinguishing
between classes, the statute either intrudes on the exercise of a fundamental
right or burdens a suspect class of persons, the court will apply a strict scrutiny
standard wherein the state must demonstrate that the challenged statute is necessary
to the achievement of a compelling state interest. . . . If the statute does
not touch upon either a fundamental right or a suspect class, its classification
need only be rationally related to some legitimate government purpose in order
to withstand an equal protection challenge. . . .128
If evidence demonstrates a racial bias in the administration of a death sentence,
and race is a suspect class, should not the court apply a strict scrutiny standard?
Likewise, if evidence demonstrates that the Connecticut death penalty scheme
is arbitrary and capricious, and life is a fundamental right,129
must not the court also apply a strict scrutiny standard? Under such a standard,
the state must demonstrate that the statute serves a compelling state interest
and that the statute is necessary to accomplish such an interest.130
The Connecticut Supreme Court has evaded any such inquiry into whether a compelling
interest exists.131 In other words, it
has failed to address whether there is any compelling state interest
which justifies the death penalty.
c. Possible Compelling State Interests
Perhaps deterrence and retribution are the two interests most widely suggested
as supporting the continued use of the death penalty.132
Deterrence is often considered the most important argument offered by death
penalty advocates.133 Some claim that
deterrence works by frightening would-be criminals. For example, the state might
say, If you cross the line, if you disregard our values, you will be punished.
Conform or be condemned. Others claim that deterrence works through sentencing
guidelines by demonstrating a moral value placed on certain criminal activities.
In other words, sentencing guidelines act as a moral Geiger counter by indicating
correlations between the values placed on certain comforts and rights inherent
in a civilized society and the criminal sanctions placed on those who threaten
these comforts or violate these rights. Regardless of the message, evidence
suggests the death penalty does not have a empirically valid deterrent effect.
Specifically, the death penalty does not in fact deter homicides more
than life imprisonment.134 Also, statistics
indicate that often the murder rate in capital states is the same as or slightly
higher than adjacent non-capital states.135
Thus, deterrence does not appear to be a valid, compelling interest or justification
for the death penalty.
As for retribution, this does tend to be a plausible argument supporting the
death penalty. As long as the crime for which one is sentenced to death is murder,
there seems to be some basis for the just deserts, make the
punishment fit the crime, or an eye for an eye approach to
justice. Yet, Albert Camus suggests that the death penalty is more cruel than
the murder or homicide for which one has been sentenced to death. He wrote:
For there to be equivalence, the death penalty would have to punish a criminal who had warned his victim of the date at which he would inflict a horrible death on him and who, from that moment onward, had confined him at his mercy for months. Such a monster is not encountered in private life.136
Putting aside the rhetoric dismissing retribution as a flawed concept, one must
assume that retribution is a legitimate, if not compelling, state interest.
However, it is unlikely that retribution can overcome the inherent racial bias
and arbitrary administration of the death penalty.
Finally, [t]he death penalty sends a counterproductive message. Politicians
regularly defend the death penalty on the ground that human life is so sacred
that to snuff it out demands the highest penalty possible. Only by using the
highest penalty, they argue, can we deter the taking of life and spread the
message that life, above all other values, is never to be taken.137
In other words, it is nonsensical to suggest that we enhance respect for
life by taking it. On the contrary, we diminish respect for life by cheapening
it. In turn, we send the very opposite message we intend to convey.
With both deterrence and retribution, the question is whether either is a compelling
state interest. Can deterrence be a compelling state interest if there is no
provable deterrent effect? Can retribution be a compelling state interest is
there is no provable retributive effect? Can either be a compelling state interest
if the message received is contrary to the message sent?
d. Making the Equal Protection Argument
A significant number of studies have demonstrated that the death penalty is
administered in a racially discriminatory manner. While this discriminatory
effect may not be intentional, Sheff suggests that a discriminatory purpose
or discriminatory intent need not be proven by a defendant. Thus, it is possible
that the Connecticut Supreme Court will not adopt the McCleskey doctrine.
Such a fortuitous signal suggests that an equal protection argument might be
successful. If life is considered a fundamental right and race is indeed a suspect
class, there is no reason why a strict scrutiny standard should not be adopted
by the court in considering the validity of the death penalty under a state
constitutional, equal protection challenge. Under such an approach, the state
must bear the burden of proving a demonstrable, compelling state interest which
justifies the death penalty. In doing so, the state could not rely on deterrence
as a compelling state interest because there is no provable deterrent effect.
Likewise, the state could not rely on retribution because there is no provable
retributive effect. Indeed, in some cases, the intended message may be the opposite
of that received. As deterrence and retribution are considered the strongest
and most common arguments supporting the death penalty, it would be nearly impossible
for the state to provide a provable compelling state interest. However, until
an equal protection argument is made under the Connecticut Constitution, the
courts response will be as elusive as the justice the death penalty seeks.
C. The Future of Death Penalty Jurisprudence in Connecticut
The interplay of a tripartite system of government in the formulation of a state
policy on capital punishment will soon be more evident than before. Since the
reintroduction of the death penalty in Connecticut, the legislature has often
attempted to broaden the discretion of both judge and jury in sentencing individuals
to death.138 Such legislation would be
a move toward pre-Furman death penalty schemes held unconstitutional
because they allowed unconstitutionally broad discretion in determining
whether the death sentence should be imposed...139
Fortunately, previous legislative efforts were thwarted by Governor Lowell Weickers
veto.140 With the election of Governor
Rowland in 1994, the State of Connecticut no longer has a governor willing to
veto legislation of this kind. Quite to the contrary, Governor Rowland favors
such legislation.141 In addition, the
Connecticut legislature continues to be intent on expanding the use of the death
penalty. These two factors could have an impact on Connecticut death penalty
jurisprudence by producing more death sentences and appeals.142
This increase will more than likely foster novel challenges to the constitutionality
of the death penalty in Connecticut. As the en banc decision of State v.
Webb indicates, Justice Berdon is no longer a lone dissenter.143
Rather, three justices believe the Connecticut death penalty scheme is unconstitutional.144
Were the composition of the court to change, the outcome could result in an
unconstitutional death penalty in Connecticut. However, this is unlikely considering
Governor Rowlands position on the death penalty. His nominations to the
Connecticut Supreme Court will more than likely be aligned with the Governor
and Legislature in their zeal for a more vitalized death penalty.
The limited number of post-Furman appeals in Connecticut is a mixed blessing.
On one hand, it significantly limits the nature and number of arguments challenging
the death penalty. This limits the ability to test new theories and jurisprudential
analysis. On the other hand, it reflects the small number of individuals who
have been sentenced to death since Furman. While a change in the political landscape
may reward academics with an increase in opportunities to publish analyses of
Connecticut Supreme Court doctrine, it more than likely will result in more
death sentences and possibly the first execution in Connecticut since 1960.
One must hope an academics argument finds a receptive majority before
the executioner begins her dance.
V. Where do we go from here?
What is it about the death penalty and capital punishment that enables individual
judges and justices to condone, for so long, capital punishment as constitutional
and then, in the twilight of their careers, declare I feel morally and
intellectually obligated simply to concede that the death penalty experiment
has failed?145 Ironically, in so
doing, they articulate beautifully what those challenging the constitutionality
of capital punishment have been arguing all along. There are two ways of interpreting
these soliloquies. First, one might assume that the change represents an acknowledgment
that the death penalty has always been unconstitutional. Second, it is possible
the individual merely recognizes that certain arguments, which at one time may
have justified the the death penalty, are no longer sound. So, what is it that
produces such a change of perspective? It might be that many members of state
judiciaries feel their judicial independence threatened. In a recent speech,
the Honorable Jon O. Newman expressed concern over recent ravings by some congresspeople
who threatened impeachment of certain justices. The impetus for the congressional
response was disagreeable decisions. Can it be that our country is indeed regressing?
Judicial review and judicial independence have been cherished government institutions
since Marbury v. Madison. On the state level, there are often confidence
votes or elections which limit the tenure of judges and justices. These
methods attempt to democratize the justice system. However, one can see how
these methods make threats to judicial independence much more oppressive. Might
confidence votes and vindictive legislative bodies be factors in
justices decisions concerning the validity of capital punishment? One
certainly hopes not.
1 In the dialogue, Socrates is quoting the Laws in the context of Critos request that Socrates escape and leave the Athens, thereby avoiding the death penalty. While Socrates quotes the Laws, he and Crito both agree that what they say is indeed correct.
2 I have phrased this sentence so as to avoid any discussion of whether life exists for our soul after we leave this earth. On two levels such a discussion does not belong in this essay. First, the death sentence is not administered in order to assure ones descent into hell or ascent into heaven, gods be willing. Rather, the finality of death is the basis on which the death sentence is offered in our justice system (ie retribution). Second, the judgment of guilty and sentence of death is a judgment and sentence of this world and does not invoke a court, inquisitor, and jury in the afterlife.
3 This author believes that human nature insists on such a law or moral sense of what is right. Therefore, even when we were in a state of nature, there was a moral imperative inherent in natural law which forbade killing another person.
4 Exodus 20:13. The use of this reference to the Bible does not indicate any argument that the Bible condones or condemns capital punishment. However, it does serve to introduce the fact that murder and killing are in fact wrong according to many religions. Again, this essay does not explore the contradictions which arise from passages such as Leviticus 24:17 and Revelation 13:10. For a discussion similar to the one avoided here, see: Ledewitz, Bruce S. and Scott Staples, Reflections on the Talmudic and American Death Penalty. 6 J. Law. & Pub. Pol'y 33 (1993).
4 The order of the names is merely a representation of their respective place in history. No claim is made here that one individual is more or less important than the other.
5 Socrates was charged and convicted of corrupting the young and of not believing in the gods in whom the city believes, but in other new divinities. Plato, Apology at 24b. Jesus of Nazareth was charged and convicted of sedition. John 18:33-:38 & 19:4-:16.
6 Here I want to check on modern countries v. those where political execution still exists.
7 The Death Penalty: Facts and Figures 1996.
8 Gregg v.Georgia, 428 U.S. 153 (1976); Proffitt v. Florida, 428 U.S. 242 (1976); and, Jurek v. Texas, 428 U.S. 262 (1976).
9 As of December 1996, the following states (jurisdictions, as the District of Columbia is included) do not have a death penalty: Alaska, District of Columbia, Hawaii, Iowa, Maine, Massachusetts, Michigan, Minnesota, North Dakota, Rhode Island, Vermont, West Virginia and Wisconsin. United States Department of Justice, Office of Justice Programs, Bureau of Justice Statistics, Bulletin: Capital Punishment 1995, December 1996. (Hereinafter referred to as the 1995 BJS Report.)
10 Governor Pataki made the reintroduction of the death penalty a campaign issue in 1994. New York State reintroduced the death penalty in 1995. In the same year, three abolitionist states survived attempts at reintroduction of the death penalty (Iowa, Massachusetts, and Wisconsin). The Death Penalty: Facts and Figures 1996.
11 Id.
12 Gregg v.Georgia, 428 U.S. 153 (1976).
13 In Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238 (1972), the Court held the death penalty to be unconstitutional as administered in those states systems which were before it.
14 In Trop v. Dulles, the Court noted in a footnote that unusual had never been distinguished from cruel. 356 U.S. 86, 101 n. 32. The Court suggested that were it necessary to do so, the meaning of unusual would probably be in its normal sense. Id. The issue in Trop was whether denationalization was violative of the Eight Amendment. The Court held it was. In footnote 32, Chief Justice Warren for the Court indicated that denationalization fit the concept of unusual. Id.
15 Wilkerson v. Utah, 99 U.S. 130, 136-37 (1878). Were the death penalty violative of the Eighth Amendment, it would be barred to the states through the Fourteenth Amendment. For such an analysis, see the discussion of Furman v. Georgia infra.
16 In re Kemmler, 136 U.S. 436, 447 (1890). The source of the Constitutional provision against cruel and unusual punishment derives from the English Declaration of Human Rights of 1688 wherein it is declared that excessive bail ought not to be required, nor excessive fines imposed, nor cruel and unusual punishments inflicted. Id. at 446, quoting 1 Wm. & Mary, 2d Sess. (1689), c. 2. Those same principles can be traced further back to the Magna Carta. Trop v. Dulles, 356 U.S. 86, 100 (1958).
17 Id.
18 217 U.S. 349 (1910).
19 Id. at 350. In Trop v. Dulles, Chief Justice Warren summarized Weems as holding that the Amendment must draw its meaning from the evolving standards of decency that mark the progress of a maturing society. 356 U.S. 86, 100 (1957).
20 See Justice Goldbergs dissent, which Justices Douglas and Brennan joined, in Rudolph v. Alabama, 375 U.S. 889 (1963). See also Weems v. United States, In interpreting the Eighth Amendment it will be regarded as a precept of justice that punishment for crime should be graduated and proportioned to the offense. 217 U.S. at __.
21 See: United States v. Jackson, 390 U.S. 570 (1968) (holding that a statute may not make the possibility of the death penalty a price to pay for a jury trial and that such a provision "needlessly penalizes the assertion of a constitutional right. Id. at 583)(but see Brady v. United States, 397 U.S. 742 (1970) holding that Jackson did not rule that all pleas of guilty encouraged by the fear of a possible death sentence are involuntary pleas nor that such encouraged pleas are invalid whether involuntary or not. Id. at 747.); Witherspoon v. Illinois, 391 U.S. 510 (1968) (holding that a sentence of death cannot be carried out if the jury that imposed or recommended it was chosen by excluding veniremen for cause simply because they voiced general objections to the death penalty or expressed conscientious or religious scruples against its infliction...No defendant can constitutionally be put to death at the hands of a tribunal so selected. Id. at 522.);
22 See Solesbee v. Balkcom, 339 U.S. 9 (1950) (holding that it is quite constitutional to leave an insanity determination to a Governor where supported by physicians reports and where such a determination will determine whether a convicted defendant will be sentenced to death); Williams v. New York, 337 U.S. 241 (1949) (holding that the Fourteenth Amendment due process clause did not require that a defendant confront witnesses who gave evidence out of court even where a jury had recommended a life sentence and the trial court sentenced a defendant to death).
23 McGuatha v. California, 402 U.S. 183, 196 (1971).
24 408 U.S. 238 (1972).
25 428 U.S. 153 (1976).
26 Patricia L. Ragone and J. Michael Williams, Conference: The Death Penalty in the Twenty-First Century, 45 Am. U.L. Rev. 239, 246 (1995).
27 Id.
28 Francis J. Mootz, III, The Ontological Basis of Legal Hermeneutics: A Proposed Model of Inquiry Based On the Work of Gadamer, Habermas, and Ricouer, 68 B.U.L. Rev. 523, 609 (1988).
29 Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 239-40 (1972).
30 Furman, 408 U.S. 238. Justices Douglas, Brennan, Stewart, Marshall, and White filed opinions in support of the judgments while Chief Justice Burger, Blackmun, Powell, and Rehnquist filed opinions against the judgments.
31 State v. Breton, 562 A.2d 1060, 1063 n.4 citing R. Rosen, The 'Especially Heinous' Aggravating Circumstance in Capital Cases -- The Standardless Standard, 64 N.C.L. Rev. 941, 948 n.40 (1986).
32 John E. Coons, Consistency, 75 Calif. L. Rev. 59 (1987).
33 Of course, this conclusion is based on the present state of Supreme Court precedent discussed above. There may come a time where the sense of public decency or morality calls for a different interpretation of the Constitution. It should also be noted that death penalty per se is used to distinguish between arguments that the death penalty is unconstitutional per se and those which argue the procedure (on any number of levels) by which the sentence was imposed may violate the guidelines articulated by the Court. In such a case, a states methodology may indeed violate the Constitution. However, an analysis of these arguments is beyond the scope of this article.
34 State v. Miller, 227 Conn. 363, 379-80 (1993).
35 The frequency with which capital punishment is used in Connecticut is quite low. Since 1977, there have been no executions in the State of Connecticut. Tracy L. Snell, Capital Punishment 1995, 1996 Bur. Just. Stat. Bull. 10. In addition, only 5 individuals were under a sentence of death as of 12/31/95. Id. at 6.
36 In State v. Ross, the court held that the due process clauses of our state constitution incorporate the principles underlying a constitutionally permissible death penalty statute that the United States Supreme Court has articulated [which] require, as a constitutional minimum, that a death penalty statute, on the one hand, must channel the discretion of the sentencing judge or jury so as to assure that the death penalty is being imposed consistently and reliably, and on the other hand, must permit the sentencing judge or jury to consider, as a mitigating factor, any aspect of the individual defendants character or record as well as the circumstances of the particular offense. Our death penalty statute, @ 53a-46a, meets these minimum state constitutional requirements. 646 A.2d 1318, 1357 (1994). It was through an analysis of these requirements that the court held that the jurys finding of no mitigating factor cannot stand because of the trial courts evidentiary and instructional rulings that did not comply with the statutory requirements of @53a-46a. Id. at 1360. As a result, the court ordered a new sentencing hearing. Id.
37 State v. Ross, 230 Conn. 183, 249 (1994)citing State v. Geisler, 222 Conn. 672, 684-86 (1992). Hereinafter, these factors will be referred to as the Geisler factors or Geisler factor.
38 See Michael J. Besso, Commentary: Commenting on the Connecticut Constitution, 27 Conn. L. Rev. 185, 206 (1994) and Martin B. Margulies, Commentary: The Uses and Misuses of History: A Reply to Michael Besso, 27 Conn. L. Rev. 231, 234 (1994). See also, Thomas Morawetz, Commentary: Deviation and Autonomy: The Jurisprudence of Interpretation in State Constitutional Law, 26 Conn. L. Rev. 635, 644-45 (1994), where the author discusses the smorgasbord approach and its limitations as observed in State v. Miller, 630 A.2d 1315 (1993).
39 Ross, 230 Conn at 249.
40 Id. citing G. Clark, A History of Connecticut (1914).
41 The last execution in Connecticut occurred in 1960. As of December 31, 1995, only five individuals are under sentence of death in Connecticut. As of April 1997, this number has increased to six.
42 According to Swift, by 1796, only seven crimes -- treason, murder, rape, bestiality, sodomy, aggravate mayhem, and arson that endangers life -- were punishable by death in Connecticut. 2 Z. Swift A System of the Laws of the State of Connecticut (1796) p. 296. Furthermore, . . . [b]y 1818, when the states constitution was adopted, bestiality and sodomy were no longer punishable by death. 2 Swifts Digest, supra, pp. 264, 292-94, 304. In 1830, the legislature removed rape and aggravated mayhem from the list of capital offenses, and reduced arson to a noncapital offense except in cases where death resulted. General Statutes (1835 Rev.) tit. 21, c.1 @@ 1-13, 156, pp. 119-21, 158. State v. Ross, 646 A2d 1318, 1376 (1994) (J. Berdon, dissenting). In 1846, the Connecticut legislature bifurcated types of murder into categories consisting of those punishable by death (murder in the first degree) and those punishable by life imprisonment (murder in the second degree). State v. Walters, 138 A.2d 786, 792-93 (1958). For a more modern example, the Connecticut legislature in 1951 replaced a mandatory death sentence with a scheme that allowed a jury to recommend a sentence of mandatory, nonpardonable life sentence. State v. Ellis, 497 A.2d 974, 977 (1985), citing Public Acts 1951, No. 369.
43 408 U.S. 238 (1972). This assertion should be qualified by acknowledging legislative action which has tended to revitalize the use of the death penalty in Connecticut.
44 State v. Martin, 506 A.2d 109, 115 (1986).
45 295 A.2d 666 (1972). The court cited Davis v. Connecticut, 408 U.S. 935 (1972) and Delgado v. Connecticut, 408 U.S. 940 (1972). Id. at 666.
46 State v. Cofone, 319 A.2d 381, 382 (1972). See also State v. Delgado, 297 A.2d 75 (1972) and State v. Davis, 316 A.2d 512 (1972) reversing earlier decisions upholding the death penalty in State v. Delgado, 260 A.2d 587 (1971) and State v. Davis, 260 A.2d 587 (1969), respectively.
47 Public Acts 1973, No. 73-137, @ 3.
48 Id.
49 See Conn. Gen. Stat. 53a-46a (1994) (Hearing On Imposition of Death Penalty: Aggravating and Mitigating Factors) (amended in 1980, 1985, 1993, and 1995). As yet, 53a-46a has not been amended to broaden the discretion of the judge and jury in sentencing an individual to death. It is worth noting that the pre-Furman Connecticut death penalty statutes were held to be unconstitutional because they allowed unconstitutionally broad discretion in determining whether the death sentence should be imposed... Cofone, 319 A.2d at 382. The legislature should be cognizant of the minimal federal guidelines acknowledged by the Connecticut Supreme Court in State v. Ross, 646 A.2d at 1318. See also Conn Gen. Stat. 53a-54b (1994) (Capital felony statute) (amended in 1977, 1980, 1985, and 1992).
50 Tracy L. Snell, Capital Punishment 1995, 1996 Bur. Just. Stat. Bull. 14. These individuals are: Michael Ross, Robert Breton, Sr.(1989), Sedrick Cobb (1991), Daniel Webb (1991), and Terry Johnson (1993). State v. Ross, 646 A.2d at 1383-84 (J. Berdon, dissenting).
51 See State v. Daniels, 542 A2d 306 (1988) (Daniels I) (holding the state has the burden of proving one of the statutorily defined aggravating factors beyond a reasonable doubt, and thereafter to impose upon the defendant the burden of proving a statutorily defined mitigating factor by a preponderance of the evidence; neither of these burdens can be met without a unanimous finding by the trier of fact; if the jury cannot agree on the existence of a mitigating factor, the trial court has discretion to declare a mistrial; [i]n such circumstances...the trial court may pursue one of three courses of action: it may declare a mistrial; it may make factual findings acquitting the defendant of the death penalty; or it may exercise its discretion...to dismiss the death penalty proceeding); State v. Daniels, 550 A.2d 885 (1988) (Daniels II) (holding the trial court did not violate the principles of double jeopardy when it imposed both a life sentence for murder and an additional life sentence for capital felony); State v. Breton, 562 A.2d 1060 (1989) (holding the aggravating factor especially cruel is not unconstitutionally vague so long as it is limited and construed so as to pass constitutional muster. Id. at 1065. Such a constitutional gloss would be the intentional infliction of extreme pain or torture above and beyond that necessarily accompanying the underlying killing. Id. at 1066).
52 State v. Ross, 646 A.2d 1318 (1994).
53 Justice Berdon, however, is an ardent supporter of the abolition of the death penalty. His dissenting opinions have recognized and articulated many of these arguments.
54 The discussion below addresses these weaknesses by examining both arguments for and against the death penalty. For purposes of clarity, arguments for the death penalty (justification arguments) have been incorporated into the discussions of those arguments challenging the facial validity of the penalty (facial arguments). This article is limited to a discussion of facial arguments. It was this authors original intent to address challenges to the manner and procedure by which death sentences are administered. However, such an analysis is beyond the scope of this article. It should be noted that non-facial arguments are significant in that they are often able to reverse a death sentence on a case by case basis. That is, while arguments challenging the facial validity of the death penalty attack the penalty itself, procedural arguments challenge the way in which death penalties are administered. In so doing, they often must focus on the particulars of the case before the court. Examples of procedural arguments include those challenging the proportionality of a death sentence (proportionality arguments) and those challenging capital sentencer requirements (capital sentencer arguments). Proportionality arguments challenge the validity of a death sentence imposed upon a defendant whos crime is not proportional to the severity (and finality) of death. Capital sentencer arguments challenge death penalty schemes where the judge or jury (depending on the case and scheme) does not understand that the determination of whether a specific human being should die at the hands of the state is its responsibility. Caldwell v. Mississippi, 472 U.S. 320, 329 (1985). In Connecticut, it has been argued that under the death penalty statute neither the judge or jury is the capital sentencer. The judge bases her decision on the jurys determination of aggravating and mitigating factors. The jury determines whether aggravating or mitigating factors exist, but never makes the specific moral judgment of whether the defendant should die. State v. Ross, 646 A.2d 1318, 1389 (1994) (J. Berdon, dissenting).
55 For example, State v. Ross articulates the majoritys analysis of the cruel and unusual argument and State v. Webb articulates the majoritys analysis of the social compact argument. This may have a lot to do with the limited number of cases addressing the constitutionality of the death penalty under the Connecticut Constitution.
56 Michael J. Besso, Commentary: Commenting on the Connecticut Constitution, 27 Conn. L. Rev. 185, 199 (1994).
57 State v. Ross, 646 A.2d 1318, 1354 (1994).
58 Id.
59 Id. at 1356.
60 Article first, section 19, as amended, of the Connecticut Constitution reads The right of trial by jury shall remain inviolate, the number of such jurors, which shall not be less than six, to be established by law; but no person shall, for a capital offense, be tried by a jury of less than twelve jurors without his consent... Furthermore, capital, as defined in 1845, included the meanings [p]unishable by loss of the head or of life; incurring the forfeiture of life; punishable with death. Websters Dictionary (Rev. ed. 1845).
61 Ross, 646 A.2d at 1356.
62 Id.
63 Id. at 1374 (J. Berdon, dissenting).
64 More appropriate precedent might have been those cases where the court had or had not recognized greater protection under the Connecticut Constitution.
65 Ross, 646 A.2d at 1356.
66 Id. citing G. Clark, A History of Connecticut (1914). But see J. Berdon dissenting in Ross, 646 A.2d at 1380-82 where a different interpretation of the same history suggests a reluctance in Connecticut to administer the death penalty. Discussed infra,
67 Ross, 646 A.2d at 1355.
68 State v. Ross, 230 Conn. 183, 249 (1994)citing State v. Geisler, 222 Conn. 672, 684-86 (1992).
69 State v. Dukes, 547 A.2d 10, 19 (1988).
70 Id. citing Gibbons v. Ogden, 22 U.S. (9 Wheat.) 1, 222, 6 L. Ed. 23 (1824) and McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. (4 Wheat.) 316, 415, 4 L. Ed. 579 (1819).
71 Ross, 646 A.2d at 1356. It is worth noting that following a beaten path may yield different results with different issues. For example, if a court has consistently provided a more restrictive definition of what is a reasonable search and seizure under its state constitution than sister states or the Supreme Court, such a beaten path may be quite appropriate depending on ones position. See e.g. State v. Joyce, 639 A.2d 1007 (1994) (holding that the Connecticut Constitution requires the police, while lawfully in custodial possession of a suspect's clothing, to obtain a warrant before subjecting the clothing to a chemical analysis. Id. at 1009). However, a court choosing to retain such a restrictive definition does not necessarily proceed in a vacuum. In any case, with any issue, a court should at least be aware of outside jurisprudence. The Connecticut Supreme Court has recognized this by employing the Geisler factors. Utilizing such an approach, the court is able to either give more weight to its own precedent and state history or give more weight to outside jurisprudence. Such an approach may make it appear that the court is picking and choosing an interpretation depending on the case and the courts disposition toward the issues raised. On the contrary, the author believes that the Geisler approach considers all the factors and by doing so provides the court with a freedom to determine the best interpretation of the state constitution. Likewise, the Geisler approach allows advocates to argue their best interpretation. This is not picking and choosing.
72 See also William A. Schabas, The Abolition of the Death Penalty in International Law (1993).
73 See Protocol No. 6 to the European Convention of the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, E.T.S. 114 (1985) (Article 1: The death penalty shall be abolished. No one shall be condemned to such penalty or executed.); Treaties, etc. here. This might suggest a seventh factor be considered when using the Geisler factors.
74 The federal system and twenty-four states have not executed a single individual since 1977.
75 Ross, 646 A.2d at 1377 (J. Berdon, dissenting).
76 Ross, 646 A.2d at 1357.
77 Id. at 1378 (J. Berdon, dissenting). While these six factors are discussed briefly here, factors three, four and five are discussed further below.
78 Id. at 1379. Justice Berdons dissent brilliantly and eloquently articulates support for each of these factors. While the author would enjoy quoting his arguments at length , space and time prohibit this. It is therefore emphatically recommended that his dissent be read in full.
79 Id. at 1380.
80 For a discussion of this factor, see infra, II. B. 3.
81 Id.
82 Id.
83 Ross, 646 A.2d at 1388.
84 45 Ala. L. Rev. 405, 425 (1994).
85 See generally Michael L. Radelet et al., In Spite of Innocence: Erroneous Convictions in Capital Cases (1992); Hugo A. Bedau and Michael L. Radelet, Miscarriage of Justice in Potentially Capital Cases, 40 Stan. L. Rev. 21 (1987); See also Stephen J. Markman & Paul G. Cassell, Protecting the Innocent: A Response to the Bedau-Radelet Study, 41 Stan. L. Rev. 121 (1988); Hugo A. Bedau and Michael L.Radelet, The Myth of Infallibility: A Reply to Markman and Cassell, 41 Stan. L. Rev. 161 (1988).
86 Tracy L. Snell, Capital Punishment 1995, 1996 Bur. Just. Stat. Bull. 15.
87 Innocence and the Death Penalty: Assessing the Danger of Mistaken Executions, Hearings Before the House Subcomm. on Civil and Constitutional Rights of the Comm. on the Judiciary, 103d Cong., 1st Sess. (1993).
88 Miller v. Warden, 1996 Conn. Super. LEXIS 874, March 27, 1996. Though Larry Miller was not on death row, evidence now suggests he is innocent and thereby wrongly convicted. As to those five sentenced to death in Connecticut between 1973 and 1995, only one sentence or conviction was overturned. Tracy L. Snell, Capital Punishment 1995, 1996 Bur. Just. Stat. Bull. 15.
89 Pure is used to denote exactness or the lack of any mistaken convictions.
90 This tension is demonstrative of the tension often found between defense attorneys and academic theorists. The defense attorneys concern must be focused on her client not the system in general. While she may utilize arguments attacking systemic problems, her arguments will no doubt be focused on the individual defendant and the present. While theorists might argue more universal critiques of the death penalty, they might not have the same viability as those arguments limited to the time and place in which they are presented to a court.
91 Ross, 646 A.2d (J. Berdon, dissenting).
92 State v. Webb, 680 A.2d 147, 160 (1996); State v. Breton, 663 A.2d 1026 (1995). The case was remanded to allow the defendant to challenge the constitutionality of execution by lethal injection.
93 Conn. Const. art. I, § 1.
94 Moore v. Ganim, 660 A.2d 742 (1995).
95 Hilton v. City of New Haven, 661 A.2d 973, 984 (1995).
96 State v. Webb, 680 A.2d 147, 160-61 (1996).
97 Hillier v. City of East Hartford, 355 A.2d 1,5 (1974) quoting Goshen v. Stonington, 4 Conn. 209, 225.
98 See Ganim, 660 A.2d at 754; Hilton, 661 A.2d at 984; and Webb, 680 A.2d at 161.
99 Webb, 680 A.2d at 161.
100 Id.
101 Id.
102 State v. Joyner, 625 A.2d 791, 802 (1993). The court bases its conclusion on that of Professor P. Hamburger, Natural Rights, Natural Law, and American Constitutions, 102 Yale L.J. 907 (1993).
103 Id. citing State v. Ross, 646 A.2d 1318 (1994). (implied prohibition against cruel and unusual punishment) and Kohlfuss v. Warden, 183 A.2d 626 (1962) (prohibition against double jeopardy).
104 While such a distinction may be worthy of more analysis, the inquiry is beyond the scope of this article.
105 Webb, 680 A.2d at 161.
106 Webb, 680 A.2d at 161.
107 See II.B.2., supra.
108 See generally, Stewart F. Hancock, Jr., et al., Race, Unbridled Discretion, and the State Constitutional Validity of New Yorks Death Penalty Statute - Two Questions, 59 Alb. L. Rev. 1545 (1996); Gregory Russell, Analyzing Racial Bias Claims After McCleskey: The Death Penalty and Racial Bias: Overturning Supreme Court Assumptions (1994).
109 Webb, 680 A.2d at 233 (J. Berdon, dissenting).
110 Stewart F. Hancock, Jr., et al., Race, Unbridled Discretion, and the State Constitutional Validity of New Yorks Death Penalty Statute - Two Questions, 59 Alb. L. Rev. 1545, 1546 (1996).
111 481 U.S. 279 (1987).
112 Id. at 285. The Eighth Amendment (cruel and unusual punishment) claim is not addressed here.
113 Id. The defendant offered a statistical study (the Baldus study) of the Georgia capital punishment system to support his claim. The Baldus study
purport[ed] to show a disparity in the imposition of the death sentence in Georgia based on the race of the murder victim and, to a lesser extent, the race of the defendant. The Baldus study is actually two sophisticated statistical studies that examine over 2,000 murder cases that occurred in Georgia during the 1970's. The raw numbers collected by Professor Baldus indicate that defendants charged with killing white persons received the death penalty in 11% of the cases, but defendants charged with killing blacks received the death penalty in only 1% of the cases. The raw numbers also indicate a reverse racial disparity according to the race of the defendant: 4% of the black defendants received the death penalty, as opposed to 7% of the white defendants. Baldus also divided the cases according to the combination of the race of the defendant and the race of the victim. He found that the death penalty was assessed in 22% of the cases involving black defendants and white victims; 8% of the cases involving white defendants and white victims; 1% of the cases involving black defendants and black victims; and 3% of the cases involving white defendants and black victims. Similarly, Baldus found that prosecutors sought the death penalty in 70% of the cases involving black defendants and white victims; 32% of the cases involving white defendants and white victims; 15% of the cases involving black defendants and black victims; and 19% of the cases involving white defendants and black victims. Baldus subjected his data to an extensive analysis, taking account of 230 variables that could have explained the disparities on nonracial grounds. One of his models concludes that, even after taking account of 39 nonracial variables, defendants charged with killing white victims were 4.3 times as likely to receive a death sentence as defendants charged with killing blacks. According to this model, black defendants were 1.1 times as likely to receive a death sentence as other defendants. Thus, the Baldus study indicates that black defendants, such as McCleskey, who kill white victims have the greatest likelihood of receiving the death penalty.
Id. at 285-87.
114 Id. at 292.
115 481 U.S. at 292 n.7.
116 Id. citing Whitus v. Georgia, 385 U.S. 545, 550 (1967) as well as Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Housing Development Corp., 429 U.S. 252, 264-65 (1977) and Washington v. Davis, 426 U.S. 229, 240 (1976).
117 Id. citing Wayte v. United States, 470 U.S. 598, 608 (1985).
118 481 U.S. 293-94. The court refers to venire selection and Title VII contexts. One difference is that statistical challenges to the capital punishment scheme implicate the involvement of many entities where the venire selection and Title VII contexts implicate a small, limited number of entities. In addition, fewer variables are relevant to the challenged decisions. Id. at 294.
119 Id. at 295-96.
120 678 A.2d 1267 (1996).
121 These discriminatory effects were de facto segregation.
122 678 A.2d 1267, 170 (1996). Specifically, the court held that the discriminatory conditions in the public school system violated Article Eighth, Section 1 and Article First, Sections 1 and 20. Article Eighth, Section 1 provides "There shall always be free public elementary and secondary schools in the state. The general assembly shall implement this principle by appropriate legislation. Article First, Section 1 provides "All men when they form a social compact, are equal in rights; and no man or set of men are entitled to exclusive public emoluments or privileges from the community." Article First, Section 20, as amended, provides No person shall be denied the equal protection of the law nor be subjected to segregation or discrimination in the exercise or enjoyment of his or her civil or political rights because of religion, race, color, ancestry, national origin, sex or physical or mental disability."
123 Id. at 1278.
124 Id. at 1278-79. See supra notes 112-20 and accompanying text.
125 Id. at 1279.
126 Both Article I, § 1 and Article I, § 20 provide have been interpreted to provide equal protection. Article I, Section 20 provides "no person shall be denied the equal protection of the law nor be subjected to segregation or discrimination in the exercise or enjoyment of his or her civil or political rights because of religion, race, color, ancestry, national origin, sex or physical or mental disability."
127 Florestal v. Government Emples. Ins. Co., 673 A.2d 474, 482 (1995)quoting Benjamin v. Bailey, 662 A.2d 1226, 1237 (1995).
128 Such an argument would not imply that life is so fundamental a right as to prohibit capital punishment. Rather, it would suggest that life is so fundamental a right that any death penalty scheme intrudes on the exercise of this right and the standard of review must, therefore, be strict scrutiny. The arbitrary and capricious nature of any particular scheme would help demonstrate the weaknesses in any alleged state interest or purpose.
129 Florestal v. Government Emples. Ins. Co., 673 A.2d 474 (1995); Cleburne v. Cleburne, Living Center, Inc., 473 U.S. 432, 440 (1985); Horton v. Meskill, 172 Conn. 640.
130 Of course, it may be the court does not reach this analysis because it does not consider the equal protection argument which would invoke the necessity for state evidence supporting a compelling state interest or purpose. Whatever the reason, the court has not addressed whether the state does indeed have such an interest. This portion of the article briefly addresses the possible absence of any such interests.
131 Hugo A. Bedau, The Case Against the Death Penalty, ACLU (1992).
132 Donald D. Hook & Lothar Kahn, Death in the Balance: The Debate Over Capital Punishment 41 (1989). Deterrence is also the predominant, political justification offered by foreign countries which still employ the death penalty. Roger Hood, The Death Penalty: A World-Wide Perspective 117 (1989).
133 Samuel Gross, The Risks of Death: Why Erroneous Convictions Are Common in Capital Cases, 44 Buffalo L. Rev 469, 472 (1996). See also Bedau citing Uniform Crime Reports 1980-1989; Jonathan Abernethy, The Methodology of Death: Reexamining the Deterrence Rationale, 27 Colum. Human Rights L. Rev. 379, 380 n.4 (1996) (The overwhelming majority of empirical studies have concluded that the death penalty is not a more effective deterrent than life imprisonment) citing William J. Bowers, Executions in America 139-45 (1974); Thorsten Sellin, The Death Penalty 23-38 (1959); Thorsten Sellin, Homicides in Retentionist and Abolitionist States, in Capital Punishment 135, 135-38 (Thorsten Sellin ed., 1967); Brian E. Forst, The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: A Cross State Analysis of the 1960s, 61 Minn. L. Rev. 743 (1977); Richard Lempert, The Effect of Executions on Homicides: A New Look in an Old Light, 29 Crime & Delinquency 88 (1983); Peter Passell, The Deterrent Effect of the Death Penalty: A Statistical Test, 28 Stan. L. Rev. 61 (1975). In addition, many studies have concluded that executions have a brutalizing effect on society because they implicitly condone the infliction of lethal violence on those who commit capital murders citing William J. Bowers, Legal Homicide 271-302 (1984). The most famous study finding support for the theory that the death penalty is a more effective deterrent than life imprisonment was by economist Isaac Ehrlich. Isaac Ehrlich, The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: A Question of Life and Death, 65 Am. Econ. Rev. 397 (1975). That study, however, was quickly and widely discredited citing Lawrence R. Klein et al., The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: An Assessment of the Estimates, in Deterrence and Incapacitation: Estimating the Effects of Criminal Sanctions on Crime Rates 336; David C. Baldus & James W. L. Cole, A Comparison of the Work of Thorsten Sellin and Isaac Ehrlich on the Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment, 85 Yale L. J. 170 (1975); William J. Bowers & Glenn L. Pierce, The Illusion of Deterrence in Isaac Ehrlich's Research on Capital Punishment, 85 Yale L. J. 187 (1975). Professor Ehrlich answered his critics and continued to advance the claim that the death penalty may be a more effective deterrent than life imprisonment. citing Isaac Ehrlich, Deterrence: Evidence and Inference, 85 Yale L. J. 209 (1975).
134 Hugo A. Bedau, The Case Against the Death Penalty, ACLU (1992).
135 Albert Camus, Resistance, Rebellion, And Death (J. O'Brien trans., 1961).
136 Rudolph J. Gerber, Death Is Not Worth It, 28 Ariz. St. L. J. 335, 351-52 (1996).
137 See supra note 50.
138 Cofone, 319 A.2d at 382.
139 Stephanie Glass, Connecticut Moves To Make Executions Easier, Reuters World Serv., Aug. 30, 1994.
140 Id. Governor Rowland would seek an expanded, enforceable death penalty bill. Id. His use of enforceable may be indicative of a middle-ground approach to the radical legislation on one hand and more restrained efforts on the other.
141 While the legislature may seek to limit the number of appeals one may file and the time in which one may do so, this will not quell those appealing a sentence of death.
142 Webb, 680 A.2d 147.
143 Id.
144 Callins v. Collins, 114 S.ct. 1127, 1128 (1994) (J. Blackmun, dissenting). In addition, United States Supreme Court Justice Powell is reported to have said, I have come to think that capital punishment should be abolished. Ross, 646 A.2d at 1386.
#